The Neurosciences Institute, San Diego, CA 92121, United States.
Phys Life Rev. 2012 Sep;9(3):285-94. doi: 10.1016/j.plrev.2012.07.001. Epub 2012 Jul 10.
Natural phenomena are reducible to quantum events in principle, but quantum mechanics does not always provide the best level of analysis. The many-body problem, chaotic avalanches, materials properties, biological organisms, and weather systems are better addressed at higher levels. Animals are highly organized, goal-directed, adaptive, selectionist, information-preserving, functionally redundant, multicellular, quasi-autonomous, highly mobile, reproducing, dissipative systems that conserve many fundamental features over remarkably long periods of time at the species level. Animal brains consist of massive, layered networks of specialized signaling cells with 10,000 communication points per cell, and interacting up to 1000 Hz. Neurons begin to divide and differentiate very early in gestation, and continue to develop until middle age. Waking brains operate far from thermodynamic equilibrium under delicate homeostatic control, making them extremely sensitive to a range of physical and chemical stimuli, highly adaptive, and able to produce a remarkable range of goal-relevant actions. Consciousness is "a difference that makes a difference" at the level of massive neuronal interactions in the most parallel-interactive anatomical structure of the mammalian brain, the cortico-thalamic (C-T) system. Other brain structures are not established to result in direct conscious experiences, at least in humans. However, indirect extra-cortical influences on the C-T system are pervasive. Learning, brain plasticity and major life adaptations may require conscious cognition. While brains evolved over hundreds of millions of years, and individual brains grow over months, years and decades, conscious events appear to have a duty cycle of ∼100 ms, fading after a few seconds. They can of course be refreshed by inner rehearsal, re-visualization, or attending to recurrent stimulus sources. These very distinctive brain events are needed when animals seek out and cope with new, unpredictable and highly valued life events, such as evading predators, gathering critical information, seeking mates and hunting prey. Attentional selection of conscious events can be observed behaviorally in animals showing coordinated receptor orienting, flexible responding, alertness, emotional reactions, seeking, motivation and curiosity, as well as behavioral surprise and cortical and autonomic arousal. Brain events corresponding to attentional selection are prominent and widespread. Attention generally results in conscious experiences, which may be needed to recruit widespread processing resources in the brain. Many neuronal processes never become conscious, such as the balance system of the inner ear. An air traveler may "see" the passenger cabin tilt downward as the plane tilts to descend for a landing. That visual experience occurs even at night, when the traveler has no external frame of spatial reference. The passenger's body tilt with respect to gravity is detected unconsciously via the hair cells of the vestibular canals, which act as liquid accelerometers. However, that sensory activity is not experienced directly. It only becomes conscious via vision and the body senses. The vestibular sense is therefore quite different from visual perception, which "reports" accurately to a conscious field of experience, so that we can point accurately to a bright star on a dark night. Vestibular input is also precise but unconscious. Conscious cognition is therefore a distinct kind of brain event. Many of its features are well established, and must be accounted for by any adequate theory. No non-biological examples are known. Penrose and Hameroff have proposed that consciousness may be viewed as a fundamental problem in quantum physics. Specifically, their 'orchestrated objective reduction' (Orch-OR) hypothesis posits that conscious states arise from quantum computations in the microtubules of neurons. However, a number of microtubule-associated proteins are found in both plant and animal cells (like neurons) and plants are not generally considered to be conscious. Current quantum-level proposals do not explain the prominent empirical features of consciousness. Notably, they do not distinguish between closely matched conscious and unconscious brain events, as cognitive-biological theories must. About half of the human brain does not support conscious contents directly, yet neurons in these "unconscious" brain regions contain large numbers of microtubules. QM phenomena are famously observer-dependent, but to the best of our knowledge it has not been shown that they require a conscious observer, as opposed to a particle detector. Conscious humans cannot detect quantum events "as such" without the aid of special instrumentation. Instead, we categorize the wavelengths of light into conscious sensory events that neglect their quantum mechanical properties. In science the burden of proof is on the proposer, and this burden has not yet been met by quantum-level proposals. While in the future we may discover quantum effects that bear distinctively on conscious cognition 'as such,' we do not have such evidence today.
自然现象在原则上可以还原为量子事件,但量子力学并不总是提供最佳的分析水平。多体问题、混沌雪崩、材料特性、生物有机体和天气系统在更高的层次上得到更好的处理。动物是高度组织化、有目标导向、适应性强、选择论、信息保存、功能冗余、多细胞、准自主、高度移动、繁殖、耗散系统,在物种水平上长时间保持许多基本特征。动物大脑由大量专门信号细胞组成的分层网络组成,每个细胞有 10000 个通信点,并且以 1000Hz 的速度相互作用。神经元在妊娠早期就开始分裂和分化,并持续发育到中年。清醒的大脑在精细的体内平衡控制下远离热力学平衡运行,使其对一系列物理和化学刺激非常敏感,高度适应,并能够产生一系列目标相关的动作。意识是“在哺乳动物大脑中最平行交互的解剖结构皮质-丘觉(C-T)系统中,大量神经元相互作用的水平上产生差异的结果”。其他大脑结构并没有直接导致有意识的体验,至少在人类中是这样。然而,对 C-T 系统的间接皮质下影响是普遍存在的。学习、大脑可塑性和主要的生活适应可能需要有意识的认知。虽然大脑经过数亿年的进化,个体大脑在数月、数年和数十年中生长,但有意识的事件似乎有一个约 100ms 的循环周期,几秒钟后就会消失。它们当然可以通过内在的排练、重新可视化或关注反复出现的刺激源来刷新。当动物寻找和应对新的、不可预测的和高度重视的生活事件时,如逃避捕食者、收集关键信息、寻找配偶和捕食猎物,这些非常独特的大脑事件是必要的。动物表现出协调的受体定向、灵活的反应、警觉、情绪反应、寻求、动机和好奇心,以及行为上的惊讶和皮质和自主唤醒时,可以在行为上观察到对有意识事件的注意力选择。与注意力选择相对应的大脑事件是突出的和广泛存在的。注意力通常会导致有意识的体验,这可能是大脑中广泛处理资源所必需的。许多神经元过程从未成为有意识的,例如内耳的平衡系统。一名航空旅客可能会在飞机下降着陆时“看到”客舱倾斜向下。即使在晚上,当旅客没有外部空间参考框架时,这种视觉体验也会发生。乘客相对于重力的倾斜通过前庭管的毛细胞无意识地检测到,前庭管充当液体加速度计。然而,这种感觉活动并没有直接体验到。只有通过视觉和身体感觉才能使其成为有意识的体验。因此,前庭感觉与准确“报告”到有意识的体验领域的视觉感知不同,因此我们可以在漆黑的夜晚准确地指向一颗明亮的星星。前庭输入也是精确的,但无意识的。因此,有意识的认知是一种独特的大脑事件。它的许多特征都已经确立,必须由任何充分的理论来解释。目前还没有非生物的例子。彭罗斯和哈梅罗夫提出,意识可能被视为量子物理学中的一个基本问题。具体来说,他们的“协调客观还原”(Orch-OR)假说假设,意识状态是由神经元中的微管中的量子计算产生的。然而,许多植物和动物细胞(如神经元)中都发现了与微管相关的蛋白质,而植物通常不被认为是有意识的。目前的量子水平提案并不能解释意识的突出经验特征。值得注意的是,它们不能像认知生物学理论那样区分密切匹配的有意识和无意识的大脑事件。大约一半的人脑不能直接支持有意识的内容,但这些“无意识”大脑区域的神经元中含有大量的微管。量子现象以观察者依赖而闻名,但据我们所知,它们并不需要一个有意识的观察者,而不是一个粒子探测器。没有特殊仪器的帮助,有意识的人类无法“原样”检测到量子事件。相反,我们将光的波长分类为有意识的感觉事件,忽略了它们的量子力学特性。在科学中,证明的责任在于提议者,而这一责任量子水平提案尚未得到满足。虽然将来我们可能会发现与意识认知“本身”有明显关系的量子效应,但我们今天没有这样的证据。